Accueil🇫🇷Chercher

Christopher Shields

Christopher Shields est professeur de philosophie à l'université Notre-Dame. Auparavant, il a été professeur à Boulder dans le Colorado et à Oxford. Il est spécialisé dans la philosophie classique notamment Aristote et Platon[1].

Christopher Shields
une illustration sous licence libre serait bienvenue
Biographie
Naissance
Nationalité
Activité
Autres informations
A travaillé pour

Œuvre

Livre

  • Ancient Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction, 2011, London, Routledge
  • Aristotle (London: Routledge, 2007)
  • Classical Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction (London: Routledge, 2003)
  • The Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, with Robert Pasnau (Boulder: Westview Press, 2003)
  • Blackwell Guide to Ancient Philosophy, ed. (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 2002)
  • Order in Multiplicity: Homonymy in the Philosophy of Aristotle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999; paperback edition, 2001)First Philosophy First: Aristotle and the Practice of Metaphysics,” in The Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy, edd. F. Sheffield and J. Warren (Routledge: 2014), 332-346

Articles

  • “Francisco Suárez,” with Daniel Schwartz, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta (2014)
  • “The Phainomenological Method in Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” in Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics, ed. E. Feser (Palgrave Macmillan: 2013), 7-27
  • “The Grounds of Logos: the Interweaving of Forms,” in Reason and Analysis in Ancient Greek Philosophy, edd. F. Miller and G. Anagnostopoulos (Springer Verlag: 2013), 211-230
  • “On Behalf of Cognitive Qualia,” in Cognitive Phenomenology, edd. T. Bayne and M. Montague (Oxford University Press: 2012), 215-235
  • “The Dialectic of Life,” Synthese 185 (2012), 103-124 (online, by subscription: here)
  • “The Unity of Soul in Suárez,” in De Anima Acta, ed. R. Friedman (Leiden, Brill: 2012), 355-378
  • “Being qua Being,” in The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, ed. C. Shields (Oxford University Press: 2012), 343-371
  • “Perfecting Pleasures: the Metaphysics of Pleasure in Nicomachean Ethics x,” in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide, ed. J. Miller (Cambridge University Press: 2011), 191-210
  • “Plato’s Divided Soul,” in The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, ed. M. McPherran (Cambridge University Press: 2010), 147-170; reprinted in Partitioning the Soul: Ancient Medieval, and Early Modern Debates, edd. K. Corcilius and D. Perler (W. de Gruyter: 2014), 15-38
  • “The Aristotelian Psychê ,” The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle, ed. G. Anagnostopoulos (Blackwell: 2010), 292-309
  • “The Priority of Soul in Aristotle’s De Anima: Mistaking Categories?” in Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy, edd. D. Frede and B. Reis (Berlin, De Gruyter: 2009), 156-168
  • “Aristotle,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta (2008)
  • “Plato and Aristotle in the Academy: an Aristotelian Criticism of Platonic Forms,” in The Oxford Handbook on Plato, ed. G. Fine (Oxford University Press: 2008), 504-526
  • “Surpassing in Dignity and Power: the Metaphysics of Goodness in Plato's Republic,” Philosophical Inquiry XXX (2008), 1-17; reprinted in G. Anagnostopoulos, ed., Socratic, Platonic, and Aristotelian Studies: Essays in Honor of Gerasimos Santas (Springer Verlag: 2011), 281-296
  • “The Peculiar Motion of Aristotelian Souls,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume LXXXI (2007), 139-161
  • “Forcing Goodness in Plato’s Republic,” Social Philosophy and Policy (2007), 21-39
  • "Unified Agency and Akrasia in Plato's Republic," in Akrasia in Ancient Philosophy, edd. C. Bobonich and P. Destrée (Brill: 2006), 117-140
  • “Plato’s Challenge,” in The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic (Blackwell: 2006), ed. G. Santas, 63-83
  • “Aristotle: Psychology,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta (2006; rev. 2010)
  • “Learning about Plato from Aristotle,” in The Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Plato, ed. H. Benson (Blackwell: 2006), 403-417
  • “Simple Souls,” in Essays on Plato's Psychology, ed. E. Wagner (Rowan and Littlefield: 2001), pp. 137-156
  • “Um Problem a Respeito de Substância e Relativo em Aristóteles,” Cadernos De História e Filosofia de Ciência 3, vol. 13 (2003), 157-176
  • “The Logos of ‘Logos’: Theaetetus 206c-210b” Apeiron 32 (1999), 107-24
  • “Philosophy of Language: the Ancient Period,” Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (London: 1998), ed. E. L. Craig, 356-361
  • “Intentionality and Isomorphism in Aristotle,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy XI (1995), edd. J. Cleary and W. Wians, 307-330
  • “The Subjecthood of Souls and Some Other Forms: A Response to Granger,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy XIII (1995), 161-176; reprinted in Aristotle: Critical Assessments vol. 1, ed. L. Gerson (Routledge: 1999), 224-236.
  • “The Stoic Lekton,” in Hellenistic Philosophy (Athens: 1994), ed. K. Boudouris, 137-148
  • “Mind and Motion in Aristotle,” in Self Movers, edd. M. L. Gill and J. G. Lennox (Princeton University Press: 1994), pp. 117-133
  • “Aristotle on the Generation of Form,” History of Philosophy Quarterly Vol. 7 (1990), 367-390
  • “Leibniz's Doctrine of the Striving Possibles,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. XXIV (1986), 343-357; reprinted in Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: Critical Assessments Vol. II ed. R. Woolhouse (Garland: 1994), 14-28

Notes et références

  1. Pierre Destrée, « Christopher Shields, Aristotle », Revue Philosophique de Louvain, vol. 109, no 1, , p. 222–223 (lire en ligne, consulté le )
Cet article est issu de wikipedia. Text licence: CC BY-SA 4.0, Des conditions supplémentaires peuvent s’appliquer aux fichiers multimédias.